Proof. Straight forward.
Proof. Straight forward.
Note. \(\phi:G\to S_X\) is known as a permutation representation of \(G\) on \(X\).
Note. If \(|X|=n\), then \(S_X\cong S_n\). So, \(\phi\) also gives a homomorphism to \(S_n\).
For example, consider a diheral group \(D_{2n}\). It acts on \(n\) vertices of \(n\)-gon, so there is a homomorphism \(D_{2n}\to S_n\). More precisely, if we let \(X=\{v_0,v_1,\dots, v_{n-1}\}\) be vertices of \(n\)-gon, and define a map \(v_i=i+1\) for \(i+1\in \{1,2,\dots, n\}\). Then we can write the elements of \(S_X\) as the elements of \(S_n\) as follow:
\(s\cdot v_0=v_1, s\cdot v_1=v_2,\dots, s\cdot v_{n-1}=v_0\)
\[\implies \phi(s)=(1 2 \dots n)\]
\(r\cdot v_0=v_0, r\cdot v_1=v_{n-1}, \dots, r\cdot v_{i}= v_{n-i}\)
\[\implies \phi(r)=\begin{cases} (2 n)(3 n-1)\cdots(\frac{n+1}{2} \frac{n+3}{2}) & \text{if n is odd}\\
(2 n)(3 n-1)\cdots (\frac{n}{2} \frac{n+2}{2}) & \text{if n is even}\end{cases}\]
Proof. Straight forward.
Note. We say that the action is faithful if \(\ker(\phi)=\{e\}\)
Proof. \(\exists x\in X \text{ such that } g\cdot x=\ell_g(x)\neq x \iff \ell_g\neq \ell_e\).
Proof. For \(g\in G\backslash \{e\}, g\cdot e=g\neq e\). So the left regular action is faithful. It implies that \(\phi:G\to S_G\) is injective. Thus, \(G = G/\ker(\phi)\cong Im(\phi) \leq S_G\) by the first isomorphism theorem. If \(|G|=n\lt +\infty, S_G\cong S_n\).
Proof. Straight forward.
Note. For \(x\in X\), \( [x]_{\sim}=\{y\in X: g\cdot x=y \; \forall g\in G\}= \mathcal{O}_x \) where \(\mathcal{O}_x\) is the \(G\)-orbit of \(x\in X\).
Proof. Straight forward.
Note. Suppose \(G\) acts on \(X\). Let \(S\subseteq X\) be the set of representatives for \(\sim_G\). Then naturally we have \[ |X|=\sum_{x\in S} |\mathcal{O}_x| \]
Proof.
Proof.
(well defined) Suppose \(gG_x=hG_x\). Then \(g^{-1}h\in G_x\). So, \(g^{-1}h\cdot x= x \implies h\cdot x =g\cdot x\).
(injective & surjective) Straight forward
Cor. If \(G\) acts on \(X\), then for \(x\in X\), \[ |\mathcal{O}_x| = [ G: G_x ] \]
Fun application Let \(G=S_n\) and \(X=\{1,\dots,n\}\). Note that the action of \(G\) on \(X\) is transitive (\(\sigma(i)=j, \tau(j)=k \implies \tau \circ sigma(i)=k\)). (Intuitively, for \(1\leq i\neq j \leq n\), there exists \(\pi\in S_n\) such that \(\pi(i)=j\) (e.g. \(\pi=(i j)\)). So \(\mathcal{O}_x=\{g\cdot x: g\in G\}=X \implies \) the action is transitive.) Thus, \(\mathcal{O}_i=X\) for all \(i=1,2,\dots, n\). So, \(|\mathcal{O}_x|=n=[G:G_i]=\frac{|G|}{|G_i|}=\frac{n!}{|G_i|}\implies |G_i|=(n-1)!\). So we can infer that the stabilizer of \(i\in X\); \(G_i=\{\pi\in S_n: \pi(i)=i\}\) is given such that \(G_i \cong S_{n-1}\).
Proof. Let \(K\) be the kernel of action of \(G\) on \(G/H\). Then it is easy to see that \(K\leq G_{eH}\). Let \(k=[G_{eH}:K]=\frac{|G_{eH}|}{K}\). Since \([G:K]=\frac{|G|}{|K|}=\frac{|G|}{|G_{eH}|}\cdot \frac{|G_{eH}}{|K|}=p\cdot k\), we have \(G/K\cong \text{ subgroup of } S_p\). So, \(|G/K|=kp \mid |S_p|=p! \implies k\mid (p-1)!\). On the other hand, \(k\mid |G|\). Since \(p\) is the smallest prime dividing \(|G|\), we must have \(k=1\). Thus, \(|G_{eH}|=|K| \implies G_{eH}=K\).
Note. If \(H\leq G\), then \(gHg^{-1}\leq G\) for all \(g\in G\).
Proof. For \(g\in G\), \(\phi:G\to G: h\mapsto ghg^{-1}\) is an automorphism. So, \(gHg^{-1}\) preserves the structure of \(H\).
Some notes on conjugation action before the proof of Sylow's Theorem